Lorenzo Cigana
University of Copenhagen (NorS)
The aim of this outline contribution, which will receive a proper treatment elsewhere, is to describe a single piece within the broader mosaic of European Structuralism: an undercurrent of Danish structural linguistics focused on the analysis of the internal organisation of linguistic categories, in both their formal and semantic constitution. The principles of such analyses were discussed and developed within the Copenhagen Linguistic Circle. According to our hypothesis, they represent an important cohesive factor that may allow us to speak of a âDanish schoolâ centred on this specific aspect.
This is mostly clear in the work of two main figures of the Copenhagen linguistic Circle, namely Viggo BrĂžndal (1887â1943) and Louis Hjelmslev (1899â1965), whose studies contributed to placing general morphology at the very heart of the Circleâs activities and interests (cf. Lejeune 1949: 126-135). Within this domain, two research directions were pursued in particular. Firstly, a semantic direction concerning the study of the so-called âfundamental meaningsâ (Hjelmslev: Grundbedeutungen, Jakobson: Gesamtbedeutungen)[1] of morphological categories, that is their semantic value. This direction can be related to proto-cognitivism as well as to some basic assumptions of phenomenology (namely Husserlâs theory of eidetic forms); furthermore, it reveals the presence of a Kantian undercurrent (Hjelmslev 1935, Burkard 2003, Fortis 2018: 172) possibly crossing not just German linguistics (see below) but structuralism as a whole. The second research direction concerned the formalisation of linguistic oppositions conceived as the underlying rationale of the former aspect. In this case, some elements can be highlighted that place this trend close to the general frameworks of logic and mereology, which were at the source of the Danish version of the so-called âtheory of markednessâ and possibly of the theory of prototypes.
We will examine these two threads more closely, connecting them to the wider panorama of European philosophical debate, before sketching a possible third thread.
Transcendental semantics towards an âempirical ontologyâ
As we have said, the first thread represents a semantic-oriented research direction: it aims to identify those general ideas that are said to be connected to morphological categories. This connection in itself was conceived rather differently by the two scholars mentioned above. According to BrĂžndal, such a connection should be regarded as generative, resembling a âdeductionâ in a Kantian sense: morphological categories arise from a meaningful substratum, that is, from a system of basic concepts ultimately belonging to those of traditional categorial philosophy (JĂžrgensen-Stjernfelt 1987) which justify their establishment on a theoretical level. As BrĂžndal himself stated, the aim of such a program was âto find in language those logical concepts that were elaborated by Aristotleâs philosophy up to modern logicâ (cf. BrĂžndal 1943: PrĂ©face). This attempt intended not just to ensure a sound and rational foundation for grammar, but to reveal its underpinning and inherently logical organization, ultimately confirming the postulate of the identity between language and thought. On the other hand, according to Hjelmslev, the same connection shall not be regarded as a foundation, but as a result of a moulding of specific content-substances by linguistic forms. Under this perspective, grammatical categories receive a semantic interpretation on the basis of the so-called âhypothesis of meaningful contentâ (Hjelmslev 1928: 163 ff.), an operational postulate according to which the semantics of grammatical categories are to be described not as pure syntactical indexes or as a set of symbolic instructions ensuring correctness of connected speech, but have to be considered as âschematic imagesâ (Cusimano 2012: 63 ff.), thus as meaningful wholes, conveying a specific sense and modelling our experience in a specific way.
We might summarize the two views by saying that BrĂžndalâs theory aimed to identify the noetic universal organization underpinning language, and could legitimately be labelled as universalistic, whereas Hjelmslevâs approach was more focused in reconstructing the linguistic, general structure of thought. Indeed, by comparing the table of grammatical categories designed by BrĂžndal[2] (see Fig. 1) to the one designed by Hjelmslev (see Fig. 2), and by temporarily disregarding their different orientation,[3] the proximity between the two models will stand out. Hjelmslevâs original and often misunderstood version of âlocalismâ â stating that case-forms constitute the common ground of both spatial and logical representations (Anschauungen) and thus modulating WĂŒllnerâs first formulation (WĂŒllner 1827, in Hjelmslev [1935] 1972: 42 ff.; cf. Fortis 2018: 172 ff.) into Wundtâs sense (Wundt 1904, in Hjelmslev [1935] 1972: 66) â is the result of such a research trend.
1) Symmetry | â | direction, tendency, irreversibility | Modus | Imperative |
â | double direction, balance, reversibility | Subjunctive | ||
2) Transitivity | . | point, moment, presupposition | Aspect | Perfective |
.. | line, duration, realisation | Imperfective | ||
3) Connexion | â | separation, past, autonomy | Tempus | Preterit |
Ă | presence, now, connection | Present | ||
4) Plurality | > | unity, concentration, convergence | Number | Singular |
< | plurality, diffusion, divergence | Plural | ||
5) Generality | Ξ | particularity, arbitrarity | Person | I |
o | generality, universality | II |
Fig. 1 â Adaptation of BrĂžndalâs table of categories from JĂžrgensen-Stjernfelt (1987)
Forms |
Substances | ||
Intense (nominal) morphemes | Extense (verbal) morphemes | ||
exclusively homonexic government | case | persona, voice | Relation
(direction, degrees of proximity, degrees of subjectivity) |
exclusively heteronexic government | comparison | emphasis | Intensity
(scalar degrees of qualities) |
both homo- and heteronexic government | number-gender | aspect-time | Consistency
(compactness, concentration, discreteness) |
alternatively homo- and heteronexic government | article | mode | Reality
(reality/unreality, desired realisation, non-realisation) |
Fig. 2 â Adaptation of Hjelmslevâs table of categories (cf. Hjelmslev 1971c: 166)
However, even if such an effort in designing a ârational semantic modelâ[4] can be regarded as quite original given the systematic way it was carried out within a proper linguistic and comparative framework, it cannot possibly be considered specific to Hjelmslev and BrĂžndal: excluding the later reception of these two models,[5] and not mentioning its pure philosophical background (Aristotle and Kant), the sources of this approach can be traced back at least to Arnaud and Lancelotâs Grammaire gĂ©nĂ©rale et raisonnĂ©e (1660)  and to a line of scholars belonging to the German tradition of Allgemeine Sprachlehre, such as Karl Leonhard Reinhold (1757â1823), August Ferdinand Bernhardi (1769â1820), Johann Gottfried Jakob Hermann (1772â1848),[6] and including also Georg Michael Roth (1769â1817) and, later on, Jacob van Ginneken (1877â1945).
Indeed, both in Rothâs Grundriss der reinen allgemeinen Sprachlehre (1815) and in van Ginnekenâs Principes de linguistique psychologique (1907), a central place is reserved for the method of justifying the categories of language on the basis of categories of thought (thus logical or psychological). In both cases, linguistic categories are said to arise from specific kinds of mental acts involving âexternal representationâ (Roth: Darstellung) or specific forms of âadheringâ to reality (van Ginneken: assent or adhĂ©sion)[7] through which the external world is organized in intentional, intersubjective experiences. Hjelmslevâs semantic analysis, given in 1934 and 1935â37, follows the same transcendental insights,[8] even if the premise is rather that linguistic forms (and not semantic ideas) are what provide the means through which noetic categorization is built up and can be analysed.
Far-reaching implications of this structural semantics trend, the elucidation of which lies beyond the aim of the present contribution, led to a change in the way the function of language is conceived: not as a mere tool for representing reality, but as the means for opening up possible scenarios and situating speakers in it, defining the very preconditions of enunciation.[9] Such a proto-pragmatist turn implies a progressive distancing from the âactantial modelâ that was so neatly summed up by TesniĂšre ([1966] 2015: § 97). Semantic analyses of linguistic categories, consistently comparable to Hjelmslevâs localistic approach, were also carried out by Paul Diderichsen (1905â1964), who worked on the general meaning of ârealityâ connected to the category of articles (Diderichsen [1939] 1966), and by Jens Holt (1904â1973) and Hans Christian SĂžrensen (1911â?), who specified the Grundbedeutung of limitation/illimitation connected to the category of grammatical aspect (cf. below).
The ultimate goal of this trend was the mapping of the âempirical ontologyâ linked to the general structure of linguistic forms (Hjelmslev [1939] 1971b: 141), ideally free from too blatant aprioristic biases thanks to the application of a watered-down principle of universality (cf. Roth 1815). This perspective can thus be seen as an application of Herderâs claim within the domain of empirical linguistic research: according to Herder, âthe only acceptable critique of cognition was [âŠ] a Sprachkritik â a study of language that analysed the conceptual resources available in natural tonguesâ (Herder Metakritik, in SĂ€mtliche Werke, XXI: 25, quoted in Benes 2008: 50).
The theory of correlative forms
The second trend will lead us to reconstruct a network of references and ideas that partially overlap with those belonging to the first, as it concerns some models of formalizing linguistic oppositions. More specifically, it is complementary to the former insofar as the semantic content of each category is said to be dependent on its internal structure. The core idea behind the models that flourished in the Thirties, and in particular Hjelmslevâs theory, is quite simple and can be summarised in the following way: (1) each linguistic unit is paradigmatically identified by its place within the system; (2) the system itself is defined as a network of oppositions; (3) the identity of each unit depends on the form of the opposition that connects (and differentiates) the unit from all the others. The effort to formalize such oppositions on the basis of a âbroader-minded logicâ (Jespersen 1924: 344) not only distinguishes Hjelmslevâs model from Jakobsonâs and Trubetzkoyâs (Cantineau 1952), but allows for a âscholastic lineageâ to become visible, connecting Hjelmslevâs (and to some extent also BrĂžndalâs) theory to what we could call the âsecond generationâ Danish linguists such as Hans JĂžrgen Uldall, Knud Togeby, Jens Holt and Hans Christian SĂžrensen, whose need for a common method in general and comparative morphology led them to borrow their mastersâ theories, and in some cases even to reshape them into partially different ones.
As the reader may know, Hjelmslevâs elaboration of a formalized system of opposition was tortuous to say the least and exacted a high toll on him, not just in terms of conceptual energy, but also in human relations: the later rift between him and BrĂžndal (Gregersen 1991, Rasmussen 1987) might have been caused by theoretical rivalry in establishing such a theory. On the one hand, Hjelmslevâs and BrĂžndalâs models are closely comparable (Rasmussen 1987, Cigana 2014), even if the specific geometry of correlates, that is the âextensional definitionâ of the two systems, does not overlap: Hjelmslev considers that each linguistic category can be established by a closed set of possible combinations of 6 terms (or 7, according to a later stage of the model), whereas in BrĂžndalâs version the number of terms is fixed at 6 and the possible combinations are less elastic. The details and the differences of the two models left aside, it is worth noticing that at some point of their work, the above-mentioned linguists began to draw concretely from the common set of assumptions on which both theories built, applying them in a critical way, and even adapting them according to their specific needs.
The issue of a possible scholastic tradition concerning this specific point was first addressed by van Ginneken, in a letter to Hjelmslev dated 25th September 1935.[10] Asking after certain details of a description proposed by Hjelmslev in La catĂ©gorie des cas (1935), he wondered if it could have been built upon BrĂžndalâs theory, which was discussed at the International Congress of Linguists (Rome, 1933). âThe point isâ, says van Ginneken, âthat he [BrĂžndal] never quotes you [Hjelmslev], and since you donât quote him either, Iâve started to think that this theory is the property of the Copenhagenâs school!â. Hjelmslevâs answer, dated 1st November 1935,[11] is just as interesting:
the system which youâre inquiring into derives indeed from BrĂžndalâs theory, yet its origins can be traced back to ancient grammars, since such a theory lies behind almost every grammatical model, whether implicitly or explicitly acknowledged. Fortunatov, PeĆĄkovskij, Karcevskij and BrĂžndal just gave a more exact formulation of it. Yet it doesnât seem to me that the school of Copenhagen can pride itself on its property: at best, it may be said that it was the Copenhagen school that gave the finishing touches. At any rate, I guess it would be fairer to acknowledge my eminent colleague for having introduced the complete and definitive theory: it is BrĂžndalâs name, not mine, that you should cite in your workâ.
In fact, the theories of linguistic oppositions were discussed at the meetings of the linguistic circle among a restricted number of members[12]: âDuring such meetingsâ, adds Hjelmslev, âBrĂžndalâs model had to reveal quickly its inadequacy in dealing with linguistic facts. I myself have tried to design a different theory which could satisfy my needs; Iâm actually quite surprised to know that he still endorses that model. This answer is striking for more reasons: firstly, although quoting the Russian tradition, Hjelmslev doesnât mention Jakobson and Trubetzkoj, who together developed the so-called âmarkedness-theoryâ,[13] a theory that competed â more or less to the same extent as BrĂžndalâs model â with Hjelmslevâs own, more complicated version, called âtheory of participative oppositionsâ. At the same time, however, he gives complete credit to BrĂžndal for being the first in this respect. It seems as if Hjelmslev were rather intrigued by the possibility of acknowledging a âCopenhagen schoolâ in the formalization of linguistic correlation, even if he explicitly rejects van Ginnekenâs suggestion.
And indeed, something like that occurred, since Hjelmslevâs model was taken up by almost all the members of the âgeneral grammar committeeâ: Jens Holt applied it in his Ătudes dâaspect (1943: 103), by describing the internal articulation of the general category of aspect, suggesting that its distinction from the category of time; more or less the same operation was carried out by Hans Christian SĂžrensen in Aspect et temps en slave (1949: 101), who reformulated it, reworking the epistemological principles of glossematics; Knud Togeby, in his famous Structure immanente de la langue française (1965: 104-106, passim), assimilates the basic insights of Hjelmslevâs model with other theories, but gave a rather syncretic perspective on the morphological classifications he used. Finally, Hans JĂžrgen Uldall adapted it according to his own needs in the Outline of Glossematics (Uldall 1967), by overgeneralizing its reach beyond Hjelmslevâs original framework. Apart from the divergences that later made Uldallâs and Hjelmslevâs approaches incompatible, the formerâs presentation allowed the epistemological underpinnings of the latterâs model to become evident. Among those, one in particular was of great importance: the principium individuationis of linguistic units (cf. Cigana & Jensen 2017: 91 ff.), which Uldall tried to harmonize with the basic assumptions of Hjelmslevâs theory of participation. The identity of linguistic units is said to be neither simply given nor fixed once for all, since it ultimately depends on the place the units come to occupy within the system. In its turn, each linguistic system exists in a state of general overlap, as the phenomena of syncretism, markedness and fusion show: due to this feature, the identity of linguistic invariants is conceived as fuzzy and permeable. In outlining the theoretical framework for this principle, Uldall draws from three sources: 1) from the notion of value given in Saussureâs Cours, 2) from a less expected analytical-aligned tradition, represented by Bertrand Russell, 3) from the philosophical debate concerning the principle of analogy, which, far from being a patent reference, lies rather in the background:
The question of identity is metaphysically thorny. Are two things ever quite the same? Is one thing ever quite the same at one moment as it was the moment before? I once had a Model T Ford which had most of its parts replaced and the rest considerably battered before I finally sold it for twelve dollars and fifty cents: was that the same car? And if not, what accounts for the continuity which there obviously was between the car I bought and the car I sold two years later? One way out is to declare firmly that all âeventsâ are unique: the Model T at one moment is not the same as the Model T at any other moment, however short the moment elected as a unit of measurement. But if science is to be possible, it is clear that this will not do: one cannot make science out of an infinity of differences; science presupposes recognisable similarities, and similarity implies identity. Our somewhat robust definition of identity has been designed to fulfil this requirement (Uldall 1967: 52-53).
Two main ideas are brought together at this point: 1) Russellâs distinction between numerical (âabsoluteâ) identity, which here is discarded as unattainable,[14] and qualitative (ârelativeâ) identity or âequivalenceâ â which is retained, since both science and experience build upon it;[15] 2) the mechanism of analogy (âsimilarityâ) that can explain how identifications are carried out both in science (by consciously taking into account only the relevant features or connections of a given entity) and in experience (by unconsciously selecting or excluding relevant features or qualia of a given entity). This reference is of no secondary significance, since it represents a necessary prerequisite of Hjelmslevâs theory of linguistic oppositions and consequently of all the above-mentioned versions that draw from it. This prerequisite states that each invariant (linguistically pertinent unit) has to be conceived as articulated into a set of variants or âqualitiesâ (such as particular meanings for content-units, or phonetic occurrences, for expression-units)[16] which can be shared by the invariants themselves, generating overlapping forms.
Sketches for an open conclusion: beyond (or behind) the Copenhagen school
As we have seen, at the bottom of this theoretical nexus lies the idea according to which linguistic functioning is grounded on a web of qualitative identities conditioned by the same mechanism that governs analogical thinking. Yet, by following the line of the âschool inheritanceâ, that is the theory of linguistic oppositions passed down from maĂźtres to pupils, another line becomes patent, which goes outwards and connects the mentioned âschoolâ to a wider network of scholars in the domains of epistemology and social sciences. This network includes among others Harald HĂžffding (1843â1931), mediating by Svend Ranulf (in his turn a very interesting figure),[17] Ămile Meyerson (1859â1933), LĂ©vy-Bruhl (whose definition of âprelogismâ was of course of paramount importance in this respect), but also more sociologically oriented scholars such as Alf Ross (1899â1979) and Ferdinand Tönnies (1855â1936). What allows all these names to be brought together is not just the fact that (scattered) references to their thought are attested across the works of the linguists mentioned above, but mostly the presence of a common factor in their reflexion: the functioning of analogical thinking (HĂžffding, Meyerson, Ranulf) as the subconscious rationale which governs not only cognitive operations but also the most elementary forms of social aggregation (LĂ©vy-Bruhl, Ross, Tönnies).
The double line that we have sketched here, concerning the discussion on the semantic and formal constitution of linguistic categories, is just a thread of a broader tapestry we would gladly discuss further. Indeed, the reconstruction of the full network of possible influences, reception or simple references that ties together the Danish linguists and their European contemporaries still lies ahead of us; yet itâs a task that has to be carried out in order to evaluate structuralism in all its facets.
Bibliography
Ablali, D. (2017), âLouis Hjelmslev en toutes lettres : Ă©lĂ©ments de rĂ©ponse au projet glossĂ©matique inachevĂ© avec Uldall dans des lettres Ă Martinet, Jakobson, Benveniste et quelques autresâ, in Chepiga, V. & Sofia, E. (eds.), La correspondance entre linguistes. Un espace de travail, AcadĂ©mia LâHarmattan, Louvain-La-Neuve: 65-85.
Benes, T. (2008), In Babelâs Shadow: Language, Philology and the Nation in Nineteenth-Century Germany, Detroit, Mich., Wayne State University Press.
Benveniste, Ă. (1970), âLâappareil formel de lâĂ©nonciationâ, Langages, 87: 12-18.
BrÞndal, V. (1943), Essais de linguistique générale, E. Munksgaard, Copenhagen.
Burkard, T. (2003), âDie lateinische Grammatik im 18. und frĂŒhen 19. Jahrhundert. Von einer Wortarten- zu einer Satzgliedgrammatik. Ellipsentheorie, Kasuslehre, Satzglieder, in Germania Latina â Latinitas Teutonica. Politik, Wissenschaft, humanistische Kultur vom spĂ€ten Mittelalter bis in unsere Zeit, Eckhard KeĂer & Heinrich C. Kuhn (eds), 781-830, Munich, Wilhelm Fink.
Cantineau, J. (1952), âLes oppositions significativesâ, Cahiers Ferdinand de Saussure, 10: 11-40.
Cigana, L. (2014), La nozione di “partecipazione” nella Glossematica di Louis Hjelmslev / La notion de “participation” dans la glossĂ©matique de Louis Hjelmslev, thĂšse de doctorat en cotutelle (UniversitĂ della Calabria, UniversitĂ© de LiĂšge).
Cigana, L. (2016), âAnalogia, paralogia e prelogismo. Svend Ranulf e il pensiero anticoâ, Janus. Quaderni del Circolo glossematico, 14: 43-70.
Cigana, L. (2017), âAt the crossroad between psychology, phenomenology and linguistics: van Ginnekenâs notion of « assent », Acta Structuralica. International Journal for Structuralist Research, Special Issue 1: 115-149.
Cigana, L. & Jensen, V. B. (2017), âGlossĂ©matique par correspondence. Hjelmslev et ses interlocuteurs (Martinet et Bazell)â, in Chepiga, V. & Sofia, E. (eds.), La correspondance entre linguistes. Un espace de travail, AcadĂ©mia LâHarmattan, Louvain-La-Neuve: 85-129.
Cusimano, C. (2012), La sémantique contemporaine. Du sÚme au theme, Paris, PUPS.
Fortis, J.-M. (2018), âAndersonâs case grammar and the history of localismâ, in Böhm, R. & van der Hulst, H. (eds), Substance-based Grammar â The (Ongoing) Work of John Anderson, John Benjamins.
Ginneken, van, J. (1907), Principes de linguistique psychologique. Essais de synthĂšse, Amsterdam,-Paris, Leipzig.
Gregersen, F. (1991), Sociolingvistikkens (u)mulighed
Herder, J. G. (1799), Metakritik zur Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in (1967), SĂ€mtliche Werke, vol. XXI
Hjelmslev, L. (1928), Principes de grammaire générale, Bianco Lunos, Copenhagen.
Hjelmslev, L. (1972), La catĂ©gorie des cas. Ătude de grammaire gĂ©nĂ©rale [1935-37] (zwei Teile in einem Band), MĂŒnich, Wilhelm Fink Verlag.
Hjelmslev, L. (1971a), Essais linguistiques, Paris, Minuit.
Hjelmslev, L. (1971b), âLa structure morphologiqueâ [1939], in Hjelmslev 1971a: 122-147.
Hjelmslev, L. (1971c), âEssai dâune thĂ©orie des morphĂšmesâ [1938], in Hjelmslev 1971a: 161-173.
Hjelmslev, L (1985a), Nouveaux essais, Paris, PUF.
Hjelmslev, L (1985b), âStructure gĂ©nĂ©rale des corrĂ©lations linguistiquesâ, in Hjelmslev 1985a: 25-66.
Holt, J. (1943), Ătudes dâaspect, Copenhagen, Munksgaard (Acta Jutlandica, XV, 2).
Jakobson, R. (1971), âBeitrag zur allgemeinen Kasuslehre Gestamtbedeutungen der russischen Kasusâ, in Selected Writings II. Word and Language, The Hague/Paris, Mouton: 23-71.
Jespersen, O. (1924), Philosophy of Grammar, London.
JĂžrgensen, H. J., & Stjernfelt, F. (1987), âSubstance, substrat, structure. Sur la controverse Ă©pistĂ©mologique qui a opposĂ© BrĂžndal et Hjelmslevâ, Langages, 86: 79-94.
Lejeune, M (ed) (1949), Actes du sixieme CongrĂšs international des linguistes, Paris, Klincksieck.
Rasmussen, M. (1987), âHjelmslev et BrĂžndal. Rapport sur un diffĂ©rendâ, Langages, 86: 41-58.
Roth, G.-M. (1815), Grundriss der reinen allgemeinen Sprachlehre, Frankfurt am Main.
SĂžrensen, H. C. (1949), Aspect et temps en slave, Aarhus, Universitetsforlaget.
Togeby, K. (1965), Structure immanente de la langue française, Paris, Larousse.
Uldall, H. J. (1967), Outline of Glossematics. A Study in the Methodology of the Humanities with Special Reference to Linguistics (Part I. General Theory), Copenhagen, Nordisk Sprog- og Kulturforlag.
Wundt, W. (1904), Völkerpsychologie. Eine Untersuchung der Entwicklungsgesetze von Sprache, Mythus und Sitte, vol. I: Die Sprache, Lepizig, Wilhelm Engelmann.
WĂŒllner, Fr. (1827), Die Bedeutung der sprachlichen Casus und Modi, MĂŒnster.
Diderichsen, P. [1939] (1966), âRealitet som grammatisk Kategoriâ, in 1966, Helhed og Struktur. Udvalgte Sprogvidenskabelige Afhandlinger, Copenhagen, GECGADS Forlag: 31-51.
TesniĂšre, L. [1966] (2015), Elements of Structural Syntax, John Benjamins.
Notes
[1] Cf. Jakobson (1971 : 23): âDie Frage der Gesamtbedeutungen der grammatischen Formen bildet naturgemÀà die Grundlage der Lehre von dem grammatischen System der Spracheâ.
[2] Even if it was never fully and consistently fleshed out by BrĂžndal himself (cf. JĂžrgensen & Stjernfelt 1987).
[3] Going from logical concepts to linguistic meanings, in one case; going from linguistic forms to concepts, in the other.
[4] One of BrĂžndalâs most important works is the Theory of prepositions. Introduction to a rational semantics (PrĂŠpositionernes Theori. Indledning til en rationel BetydningslĂŠre, 1940, published in French in 1950).
[5] For example, Jens Holt (1904â1973) produced a Rationel Semantik (Pleremik), published in 1946.
[6] See Benes (2008: 49 ff.)
[7] See Cigana (2017).
[8] As is clearly denoted by the use of the term Anschauung, directly borrowed from a Kantian theoretical framework and denoting the âideasâ linked to morphological categories.
[9] Or its formal apparatus, as Benveniste has it (Benveniste 1970).
[10] The French original, quoted in Rasmussen 1987 and Ablali (2017), and is deposited in Hjelmslevâs archives at the Royal Library of Copenhagen.
[11] The original letter, in French, is deposited in Hjelmslevâs archives at the Royal Library of Copenhagen (cf. Rasmussen 1987 and Ablali 2017).
[12] A possible reference to the âcomitĂ© de grammaire gĂ©nĂ©raleâ instituted in 1931 within the Linguistic Circle (cf. Bulletin du Cercle linguistique de Copenhague, 2, 1935: 13-15).
[13] He gave a quite thorough account of it in the paper âStructure gĂ©nĂ©rale des corrĂ©lations linguistiquesâ (cf. Hjemslev 1985b), though.
[14] Cf. âThe belief in absolute identity seems to me a piece of superfluous mysticism â harmless if it is not allowed to prey on the mind, but bearing the seeds of dark and hideous insanityâ (Uldall 1967: 54 [53, n. 1]).
[15] Uldallâs inclusion of such distincion in the domain of semiotics and linguistics thus precedes the treatment by J. L. Prieto, cf. Cigana & Jensen 2017: 95.
[16] For instance, in Latin, the particular meanings âinstrumentalâ, âlocativeâ, âcausalâ, etc. are conceived as variants of the corresponding invariant, the âablativeâ (cf. Hjelmslev 1935).
[17] Cf. Cigana 2016.
How to cite this post
Cigana, Lorenzo. The formalisation of grammatical meanings in Copenhagen structural linguistics. Some remarks. History and Philosophy of the Language Sciences. https://hiphilangsci.net/2019/06/14/formalisation_copenhagen
Leave a Reply